hand, where we waited
till you were up to let you know what had happened to us."
That was all I said. But before any one could speak Emile, approaching
Sophy, raised his voice and said with greater firmness than I expected,
"Sophy, my fate is in your hands, as you very well know. You may
condemn me to die of grief; but do not hope to make me forget the rights
of humanity; they are even more sacred in my eyes than your own rights;
I will never renounce them for you."
For all answer, Sophy rose, put her arm round his neck, and kissed him
on the cheek; then offering him her hand with inimitable grace she said
to him, "Emile, take this hand; it is yours. When you will, you
shall be my husband and my master; I will try to be worthy of that honour."
Scarcely had she kissed him, when her delighted father clapped his hands
calling, "Encore, encore," and Sophy without further ado,
kissed him twice on the other cheek; but afraid of what she had done
she took refuge at once in her mother's arms and hid her blushing face
on the maternal bosom.
I will not describe our happiness; everybody will feel with us. After
dinner Sophy asked if it were too far to go and see the poor invalids.
It was her wish and it was a work of mercy. When we got there we found
them both in bed--Emile had sent for a second bedstead; there were people
there to look after them--Emile had seen to it. But in spite of this
everything was so untidy that they suffered almost as much from discomfort
as from their condition. Sophy asked for one of the good wife's aprons
and set to work to make her more comfortable in her bed; then she did
as much for the man; her soft and gentle hand seemed to find out what
was hurting them and how to settle them into less painful positions.
Her very presence seemed to make them more comfortable; she seemed to
guess what was the matter. This fastidious girl was not disgusted by
the dirt or smells, and she managed to get rid of both without disturbing
the sick people. She who had always appeared so modest and sometimes
so disdainful, she who would not for all the world have touched a man's
bed with her little finger, lifted the sick man and changed his linen
without any fuss, and placed him to rest in a more comfortable position.
The zeal of charity is of more value than modesty. What she did was
done so skilfully and with such a light touch that he felt better almost
without knowing she had touched him. Husband and wife mingled their
blessings upon the kindly girl who tended, pitied, and consoled them.
She was an angel from heaven come to visit them; she was an angel in
face and manner, in gentleness and goodness. Emile was greatly touched
by all this and he watched her without speaking. O man, love thy helpmeet.
God gave her to relieve thy sufferings, to comfort thee in thy troubles.
This is she!
The new-born baby was baptised. The two lovers were its god-parents,
and as they held it at the font they were longing, at the bottom of
their hearts, for the time when they should have a child of their own
to be baptised. They longed for their wedding day; they thought it was
close at hand; all Sophy's scruples had vanished, but mine remained.
They had not got so far as they expected; every one must have his turn.
One morning when they had not seen each other for two whole days, I
entered Emile's room with a letter in my hands, and looking fixedly
at him I said to him, "What would you do if some one told you Sophy
were dead?" He uttered a loud cry, got up and struck his hands
together, and without saying a single word, he looked at me with eyes
of desperation. "Answer me," I continued with the same calmness.
Vexed at my composure, he then approached me with eyes blazing with
anger; and checking himself in an almost threatening attitude, "What
would I do? I know not; but this I do know, I would never set eyes again
upon the person who brought me such news." "Comfort yourself,"
said I, smiling, "she lives, she is well, and they are expecting
us this evening. But let us go for a short walk and we can talk things
over."
The passion which engrosses him will no longer permit him to devote
himself as in former days to discussions of pure reason; this very passion
must be called to our aid if his attention is to be given to my teaching.
That is why I made use of this terrible preface; I am quite sure he
will listen to me now.
"We must be happy, dear Emile; it is the end of every feeling creature;
it is the first desire taught us by nature, and the only one which never
leaves us. But where is happiness? Who knows? Every one seeks it, and
no one finds it. We spend our lives in the search and we die before
the end is attained. My young friend, when I took you, a new-born infant,
in my arms, and called God himself to witness to the vow I dared to
make that I would devote my life to the happiness of your life, did
I know myself what I was undertaking? No; I only knew that in making
you happy, I was sure of my own happiness. By making this useful inquiry
on your account, I made it for us both.
"So long as we do not know what to do, wisdom consists in doing
nothing. Of all rules there is none so greatly needed by man, and none
which he is less able to obey. In seeking happiness when we know not
where it is, we are perhaps getting further and further from it, we
are running as many risks as there are roads to choose from. But it
is not every one that can keep still. Our passion for our own well-being
makes us so uneasy, that we would rather deceive ourselves in the search
for happiness than sit still and do nothing; and when once we have left
the place where we might have known happiness, we can never return.
"In ignorance like this I tried to avoid a similar fault. When
I took charge of you I decided to take no useless steps and to prevent
you from doing so too. I kept to the path of nature, until she should
show me the path of happiness. And lo! their paths were the same, and
without knowing it this was the path I trod.
"Be at once my witness and my judge; I will never refuse to accept
your decision. Your early years have not been sacrificed to those that
were to follow, you have enjoyed all the good gifts which nature bestowed
upon you. Of the ills to which you were by nature subject, and from
which I could shelter you, you have only experienced such as would harden
you to bear others. You have never suffered any evil, except to escape
a greater. You have known neither hatred nor servitude. Free and happy,
you have remained just and kindly; for suffering and vice are inseparable,
and no man ever became bad until he was unhappy. May the memory of your
childhood remain with you to old age! I am not afraid that your kind
heart will ever recall the hand that trained it without a blessing upon
it.
"When you reached the age of reason, I secured you from the influence
of human prejudice; when your heart awoke I preserved you from the sway
of passion. Had I been able to prolong this inner tranquillity till
your life's end, my work would have been secure, and you would have
been as happy as man can be; but, my dear Emile, in vain did I dip you
in the waters of Styx, I could not make you everywhere invulnerable;
a fresh enemy has appeared, whom you have not yet learnt to conquer,
and from whom I cannot save you. That enemy is yourself. Nature and
fortune had left you free. You could face poverty, you could bear bodily
pain; the sufferings of the heart were unknown to you; you were then
dependent on nothing but your position as a human being; now you depend
on all the ties you have formed for yourself; you have learnt to desire,
and you are now the slave of your desires. Without any change in yourself,
without any insult, any injury to yourself, what sorrows may attack
your soul, what pains may you suffer without sickness, how many deaths
may you die and yet live! A lie, an error, a suspicion, may plunge you
in despair.
"At the theatre you used to see heroes, abandoned to depths of
woe, making the stage re-echo with their wild cries, lamenting like
women, weeping like children, and thus securing the applause of the
audience. Do you remember how shocked you were by those lamentations,
cries, and groans, in men from whom one would only expect deeds of constancy
and heroism. 'Why,' said you, 'are those the patterns we are to follow,
the models set for our imitation! Are they afraid man will not be small
enough, unhappy enough, weak enough, if his weakness is not enshrined
under a false show of virtue.' My young friend, henceforward you must
be more merciful to the stage; you have become one of those heroes.
"You know how to suffer and to die; you know how to bear the heavy
yoke of necessity in ills of the body, but you have not yet learnt to
give a law to the desires of your heart; and the difficulties of life
arise rather from our affections than from our needs. Our desires are
vast, our strength is little better than nothing. In his wishes man
is dependent on many things; in himself he is dependent on nothing,
not even on his own life; the more his connections are multiplied, the
greater his sufferings. Everything upon earth has an end; sooner or
later all that we love escapes from our fingers, and we behave as if
it would last for ever. What was your terror at the mere suspicion of
Sophy's death? Do you suppose she will live for ever? Do not young people
of her age die? She must die, my son, and perhaps before you. Who knows
if she is alive at this moment? Nature meant you to die but once; you
have prepared a second death for yourself.
"A slave to your unbridled passions, how greatly are you to be
pitied! Ever privations, losses, alarms; you will not even enjoy what
is left. You will possess nothing because of the fear of losing it;
you will never be able to satisfy your passions, because you desired
to follow them continually. You will ever be seeking that which will
fly before you; you will be miserable and you will become wicked. How
can you be otherwise, having no care but your unbridled passions! If
you cannot put up with involuntary privations how will you voluntarily
deprive yourself? How can you sacrifice desire to duty, and resist your
heart in order to listen to your reason? You would never see that man
again who dared to bring you word of the death of your mistress; how
would you behold him who would deprive you of her living self, him who
would dare to tell you, 'She is dead to you, virtue puts a gulf between
you'? If you must live with her whatever happens, whether Sophy is married
or single, whether you are free or not, whether she loves or hates you,
whether she is given or refused to you, no matter, it is your will and
you must have her at any price. Tell me then what crime will stop a
man who has no law but his heart's desires, who knows not how to resist
his own passions.
"My son, there is no happiness without courage, nor virtue without
a struggle. The word virtue is derived from a word signifying strength,
and strength is the foundation of all virtue. Virtue is the heritage
of a creature weak by nature but strong by will; that is the whole merit
of the righteous man; and though we call God good we do not call Him
virtuous, because He does good without effort. I waited to explain the
meaning of this word, so often profaned, until you were ready to understand
me. As long as virtue is quite easy to practise, there is little need
to know it. This need arises with the awakening of the passions; your
time has come.
"When I brought you up in all the simplicity of nature, instead
of preaching disagreeable duties, I secured for you immunity from the
vices which make such duties disagreeable; I made lying not so much
hateful as unnecessary in your sight; I taught you not so much to give
others their due, as to care little about your own rights; I made you
kindly rather than virtuous. But the kindly man is only kind so long
as he finds it pleasant; kindness falls to pieces at the shook of human
passions; the kindly man is only kind to himself.
"What is meant by a virtuous man? He who can conquer his affections;
for then he follows his reason, his conscience; he does his duty; he
is his own master and nothing can turn him from the right way. So far
you have had only the semblance of liberty, the precarious liberty of
the slave who has not received his orders. Now is the time for real
freedom; learn to be your own master; control your heart, my Emile,
and you will be virtuous.
"There is another apprenticeship before you, an apprenticeship
more difficult than the former; for nature delivers us from the evils
she lays upon us, or else she teaches us to submit to them; but she
has no message for us with regard to our self-imposed evils; she leaves
us to ourselves; she leaves us, victims of our own passions, to succumb
to our vain sorrows, to pride ourselves on the tears of which we should
be ashamed.
"This is your first passion. Perhaps it is the only passion worthy
of you. If you can control it like a man, it will be the last; you will
be master of all the rest, and you will obey nothing but the passion
for virtue.
"There is nothing criminal in this passion; I know it; it is as
pure as the hearts which experience it. It was born of honour and nursed
by innocence. Happy lovers! for you the charms of virtue do but add
to those of love; and the blessed union to which you are looking forward
is less the reward of your goodness than of your affection. But tell
me, O truthful man, though this passion is pure, is it any the less
your master? Are you the less its slave? And if to-morrow it should
cease to be innocent, would you strangle it on the spot? Now is the
time to try your strength; there is no time for that in hours of danger.
These perilous efforts should be made when danger is still afar. We
do not practise the use of our weapons when we are face to face with
the enemy, we do that before the war; we come to the battle-field ready
prepared.
"It is a mistake to classify the passions as lawful and unlawful,
so as to yield to the one and refuse the other. All alike are good if
we are their masters; all alike are bad if we abandon ourselves to them.
Nature forbids us to extend our relations beyond the limits of our strength;
reason forbids us to want what we cannot get, conscience forbids us,
not to be tempted, but to yield to temptation. To feel or not to feel
a passion is beyond our control, but we can control ourselves. Every
sentiment under our own control is lawful; those which control us are
criminal. A man is not guilty if he loves his neighbour's wife, provided
he keeps this unhappy passion under the control of the law of duty;
he is guilty if he loves his own wife so greatly as to sacrifice everything
to that love.
"Do not expect me to supply you with lengthy precepts of morality,
I have only one rule to give you which sums up all the rest. Be a man;
restrain your heart within the limits of your manhood. Study and know
these limits; however narrow they may be, we are not unhappy within
them; it is only when we wish to go beyond them that we are unhappy,
only when, in our mad passions, we try to attain the impossible; we
are unhappy when we forget our manhood to make an imaginary world for
ourselves, from which we are always slipping back into our own. The
only good things, whose loss really affects us, are those which we claim
as our rights. If it is clear that we cannot obtain what we want, our
mind turns away from it; wishes without hope cease to torture us. A
beggar is not tormented by a desire to be a king; a king only wishes
to be a god when he thinks himself more than man.
"The illusions of pride are the source of our greatest ills; but
the contemplation of human suffering keeps the wise humble. He keeps
to his proper place and makes no attempt to depart from it; he does
not waste his strength in getting what he cannot keep; and his whole
strength being devoted to the right employment of what he has, he is
in reality richer and more powerful in proportion as he desires less
than we. A man, subject to death and change, shall I forge for myself
lasting chains upon this earth, where everything changes and disappears,
whence I myself shall shortly vanish! Oh, Emile! my son! if I were to
lose you, what would be left of myself? And yet I must learn to lose
you, for who knows when you may be taken from me?
"Would you live in wisdom and happiness, fix your heart on the
beauty that is eternal; let your desires be limited by your position,
let your duties take precedence of your wishes; extend the law of necessity
into the region of morals; learn to lose what may be taken from you;
learn to forsake all things at the command of virtue, to set yourself
above the chances of life, to detach your heart before it is torn in
pieces, to be brave in adversity so that you may never be wretched,
to be steadfast in duty that you may never be guilty of a crime. Then
you will be happy in spite of fortune, and good in spite of your passions.
You will find a pleasure that cannot be destroyed, even in the possession
of the most fragile things; you will possess them, they will not possess
you, and you will realise that the man who loses everything, only enjoys
what he knows how to resign. It is true you will not enjoy the illusions
of imaginary pleasures, neither will you feel the sufferings which are
their result. You will profit greatly by this exchange, for the sufferings
are real and frequent, the pleasures are rare and empty. Victor over
so many deceitful ideas, you will also vanquish the idea that attaches
such an excessive value to life. You will spend your life in peace,
and you will leave it without terror; you will detach yourself from
life as from other things. Let others, horror-struck, believe that when
this life is ended they cease to be; conscious of the nothingness of
life, you will think that you are but entering upon the true life. To
the wicked, death is the close of life; to the just it is its dawn."
Emile heard me with attention not unmixed with anxiety. After such a
startling preface he feared some gloomy conclusion. He foresaw that
when I showed him how necessary it is to practise the strength of the
soul, I desired to subject him to this stern discipline; he was like
a wounded man who shrinks from the surgeon, and fancies he already feels
the painful but healing touch which will cure the deadly wound.
Uncertain, anxious, eager to know what I am driving at, he does not
answer, he questions me but timidly. "What must I do?" says
he almost trembling, not daring to raise his eyes. "What must you
do?" I reply firmly. "You must leave Sophy." "What
are you saying?" he exclaimed angrily. "Leave Sophy, leave
Sophy, deceive her, become a traitor, a villain, a perjurer!" "Why!"
I continue, interrupting him; "does Emile suppose I shall teach
him to deserve such titles?" "No," he continued with
the same vigour. "Neither you nor any one else; I am capable of
preserving your work; I shall not deserve such reproaches."
I was prepared for this first outburst; I let it pass unheeded. If I
had not the moderation I preach it would not be much use preaching it!
Emile knows me too well to believe me capable of demanding any wrong
action from him, and he knows that it would be wrong to leave Sophy,
in the sense he attaches to the phrase. So he waits for an explanation.
Then I resume my speech.
"My dear Emile, do you think any man whatsoever can be happier
than you have been for the last three months? If you think so, undeceive
yourself. Before tasting the pleasures of life you have plumbed the
depths of its happiness. There is nothing more than you have already
experienced. The joys of sense are soon over; habit invariably destroys
them. You have tasted greater joys through hope than you will ever enjoy
in reality. The imagination which adorns what we long for, deserts its
possession. With the exception of the one self-existing Being, there
is nothing beautiful except that which is not. If that state could have
lasted for ever, you would have found perfect happiness. But all that
is related to man shares his decline; all is finite, all is fleeting
in human life, and even if the conditions which make us happy could
be prolonged for ever, habit would deprive us of all taste for that
happiness. If external circumstances remain unchanged, the heart changes;
either happiness forsakes us, or we forsake her.
"During your infatuation time has passed unheeded. Summer is over,
winter is at hand. Even if our expeditions were possible, at such a
time of year they would not be permitted. Whether we wish it or no,
we shall have to change our way of life; it cannot continue. I read
in your eager eyes that this does not disturb you greatly; Sophy's confession
and your own wishes suggest a simple plan for avoiding the snow and
escaping the journey. The plan has its advantages, no doubt; but when
spring returns, the snow will melt and the marriage will remain; you
must reckon for all seasons.
"You wish to marry Sophy and you have only known her five months!
You wish to marry her, not because she is a fit wife for you, but because
she pleases you; as if love were never mistaken as to fitness, as if
those, who begin with love, never ended with hatred! I know she is virtuous;
but is that enough? Is fitness merely a matter of honour? It is not
her virtue I misdoubt, it is her disposition. Does a woman show her
real character in a day? Do you know how often you must have seen her
and under what varying conditions to really know her temper? Is four
months of liking a sufficient pledge for the rest of your life? A couple
of months hence you may have forgotten her; as soon as you are gone
another may efface your image in her heart; on your return you may find
her as indifferent as you have hitherto found her affectionate. Sentiments
are not a matter of principle; she may be perfectly virtuous and yet
cease to love you. I am inclined to think she will be faithful and true;
but who will answer for her, and who will answer for you if you are
not put to the proof? Will you postpone this trial till it is too late,
will you wait to know your true selves till parting is no longer possible?
"Sophy is not eighteen, and you are barely twenty-two; this is
the age for love, but not for marriage. What a father and mother for
a family! If you want to know how to bring up children, you should at
least wait till you yourselves are children no longer. Do you not know
that too early motherhood has weakened the constitution, destroyed the
health, and shortened the life of many young women? Do you not know
that many children have always been weak and sickly because their mother
was little more than a child herself? When mother and child are both
growing, the strength required for their growth is divided, and neither
gets all that nature intended; are not both sure to suffer? Either I
know very little of Emile, or he would rather wait and have a healthy
wife and children, than satisfy his impatience at the price of their
life and health.
"Let us speak of yourself. You hope to be a husband and a father;
have you seriously considered your duties? When you become the head
of a family you will become a citizen of your country. And what is a
citizen of the state? What do you know about it? You have studied your
duties as a man, but what do you know of the duties of a citizen? Do
you know the meaning of such terms as government, laws, country? Do
you know the price you must pay for life, and for what you must be prepared
to die? You think you know everything, when you really know nothing
at all. Before you take your place in the civil order, learn to perceive
and know what is your proper place.
"Emile, you must leave Sophy; I do not bid you forsake her; if
you were capable of such conduct, she would be only too happy not to
have married you; you must leave her in order to return worthy of her.
Do not be vain enough to think yourself already worthy. How much remains
to be done! Come and fulfil this splendid task; come and learn to submit
to absence; come and earn the prize of fidelity, so that when you return
you may indeed deserve some honour, and may ask her hand not as a favour
but as a reward."
Unaccustomed to struggle with himself, untrained to desire one thing
and to will another, the young man will not give way; he resists, he
argues. Why should he refuse the happiness which awaits him? Would he
not despise the hand which is offered him if he hesitated to accept
it? Why need he leave her to learn what he ought to know? And if it
were necessary to leave her why not leave her as his wife with a certain
pledge of his return? Let him be her husband, and he is ready to follow
me; let them be married and he will leave her without fear. "Marry
her in order to leave her, dear Emile! what a contradiction! A lover
who can leave his mistress shows himself capable of great things; a
husband should never leave his wife unless through necessity. To cure
your scruples, I see the delay must be involuntary on your part; you
must be able to tell Sophy you leave her against your will. Very well,
be content, and since you will not follow the commands of reason, you
must submit to another master. You have not forgotten your promise.
Emile, you must leave Sophy; I will have it."
For a moment or two he was downcast, silent, and thoughtful, then looking
me full in the face he said, "When do we start?" "In
a week's time," I replied; "Sophy must be prepared for our
going. Women are weaker than we are, and we must show consideration
for them; and this parting is not a duty for her as it is for you, so
she may be allowed to bear it less bravely."
The temptation to continue the daily history of their love up to the
time of their separation is very great; but I have already presumed
too much upon the good nature of my readers; let us abridge the story
so as to bring it to an end. Will Emile face the situation as bravely
at his mistress' feet as he has done in conversation with his friend?
I think he will; his confidence is rooted in the sincerity of his love.
He would be more at a loss with her, if it cost him less to leave her;
he would leave her feeling himself to blame, and that is a difficult
part for a man of honour to play; but the greater the sacrifice, the
more credit he demands for it in the sight of her who makes it so difficult.
He has no fear that she will misunderstand his motives. Every look seems
to say, "Oh, Sophy, read my heart and be faithful to me; your lover
is not without virtue."
Sophy tries to bear the unforeseen blow with her usual pride and dignity.
She tries to seem as if she did not care, but as the honours of war
are not hers, but Emile's, her strength is less equal to the task. She
weeps, she sighs against her will, and the fear of being forgotten embitters
the pain of parting. She does not weep in her lover's sight, she does
not let him see her terror; she would die rather than utter a sigh in
his presence. I am the recipient of her lamentations, I behold her tears,
it is I who am supposed to be her confidant. Women are very clever and
know how to conceal their cleverness; the more she frets in private,
the more pains she takes to please me; she feels that her fate is in
my hands.
I console and comfort her; I make myself answerable for her lover, or
rather for her husband; let her be as true to him as he to her and I
promise they shall be married in two years' time. She respects me enough
to believe that I do not want to deceive her. I am guarantor to each
for the other. Their hearts, their virtue, my honesty, the confidence
of their parents, all combine to reassure them. But what can reason
avail against weakness? They part as if they were never to meet again.
Then it is that Sophy recalls the regrets of Eucharis, and fancies herself
in her place. Do not let us revive that fantastic affection during his
absence "Sophy," say I one day, "exchange books with
Emile; let him have your Telemachus that he may learn to be like him,
and let him give you his Spectator which you enjoy reading. Study the
duties of good wives in it, and remember that in two years' time you
will undertake those duties." The exchange gave pleasure to both
and inspired them with confidence. At last the sad day arrived and they
must part.
Sophy's worthy father, with whom I had arranged the whole business,
took affectionate leave of me, and taking me aside, he spoke seriously
and somewhat emphatically, saying, "I have done everything to please
you; I knew I had to do with a man of honour; I have only one word to
say. Remembering your pupil has signed his contract of marriage on my
daughter's lips."
What a difference in the behaviour of the two lovers! Emile, impetuous,
eager, excited, almost beside himself, cries aloud and sheds torrents
of tears upon the hands of father, mother, and daughter; with sobs he
embraces every one in the house and repeats the same thing over and
over again in a way that would be ludicrous at any other time. Sophy,
pale, sorrowful, doleful, and heavy-eyed, remains quiet without a word
or a tear, she sees no one, not even Emile. In vain he takes her hand,
and clasps her in his arms; she remains motionless, unheeding his tears,
his caresses, and everything he does; so far as she is concerned, he
is gone already. A sight more moving than the prolonged lamentations
and noisy regrets of her lover! He sees, he feels, he is heartbroken.
I drag him reluctantly away; if I left him another minute, he would
never go. I am delighted that he should carry this touching picture
with him. If he should ever be tempted to forget what is due to Sophy,
his heart must have strayed very far indeed if I cannot bring it back
to her by recalling her as he saw her last.
OF
TRAVEL
Is it good for young people to travel? The question is often asked and
as often hotly disputed. If it were stated otherwise--Are men the better
for having travelled?--perhaps there would be less difference of opinion.
The misuse of books is the death of sound learning. People think they
know what they have read, and take no pains to learn. Too much reading
only produces a pretentious ignoramus. There was never so much reading
in any age as the present, and never was there less learning; in no
country of Europe are so many histories and books of travel printed
as in France, and nowhere is there less knowledge of the mind and manners
of other nations. So many books lead us to neglect the book of the world;
if we read it at all, we keep each to our own page. If the phrase, "Can
one become a Persian," were unknown to me, I should suspect on
hearing it that it came from the country where national prejudice is
most prevalent and from the sex which does most to increase it.
A Parisian thinks he has a knowledge of men and he knows only Frenchmen;
his town is always full of foreigners, but he considers every foreigner
as a strange phenomenon which has no equal in the universe. You must
have a close acquaintance with the middle classes of that great city,
you must have lived among them, before you can believe that people could
be at once so witty and so stupid. The strangest thing about it is that
probably every one of them has read a dozen times a description of the
country whose inhabitants inspire him with such wonder.
To discover the truth amidst our own prejudices and those of the authors
is too hard a task. I have been reading books of travels all my life,
but I never found two that gave me the same idea of the same nation.
On comparing my own scanty observations with what I have read, I have
decided to abandon the travellers and I regret the time wasted in trying
to learn from their books; for I am quite convinced that for that sort
of study, seeing not reading is required. That would be true enough
if every traveller were honest, if he only said what he saw and believed,
and if truth were not tinged with false colours from his own eyes. What
must it be when we have to disentangle the truth from the web of lies
and ill-faith?
Let us leave the boasted resources of books to those who are content
to use them. Like the art of Raymond Lully they are able to set people
chattering about things they do not know. They are able to set fifteen-year-old
Platos discussing philosophy in the clubs, and teaching people the customs
of Egypt and the Indies on the word of Paul Lucas or Tavernier.
I maintain that it is beyond dispute that any one who has only seen
one nation does not know men; he only knows those men among whom he
has lived. Hence there is another way of stating the question about
travel: "Is it enough for a well-educated man to know his fellow-countrymen,
or ought he to know mankind in general?" Then there is no place
for argument or uncertainty. See how greatly the solution of a difficult
problem may depend on the way in which it is stated.
But is it necessary to travel the whole globe to study mankind? Need
we go to Japan to study Europeans? Need we know every individual before
we know the species? No, there are men so much alike that it is not
worth while to study them individually. When you have seen a dozen Frenchmen
you have seen them all. Though one cannot say as much of the English
and other nations, it is, however, certain that every nation has its
own specific character, which is derived by induction from the study,
not of one, but many of its members. He who has compared a dozen nations
knows men, just he who has compared a dozen Frenchmen knows the French.
To acquire knowledge it is not enough to travel hastily through a country.
Observation demands eyes, and the power of directing them towards the
object we desire to know. There are plenty of people who learn no more
from their travels than from their books, because they do not know how
to think; because in reading their mind is at least under the guidance
of the author, and in their travels they do not know how to see for
themselves. Others learn nothing, because they have no desire to learn.
Their object is so entirely different, that this never occurs to them;
it is very unlikely that you will see clearly what you take no trouble
to look for. The French travel more than any other nation, but they
are so taken up with their own customs, that everything else is confused
together. There are Frenchmen in every corner of the globe. In no country
of the world do you find more people who have travelled than in France.
And yet of all the nations of Europe, that which has seen most, knows
least. The English are also travellers, but they travel in another fashion;
these two nations must always be at opposite extremes. The English nobility
travels, the French stays at home; the French people travel, the English
stay at home. This difference does credit, I think, to the English.
The French almost always travel for their own ends; the English do not
seek their fortune in other lands, unless in the way of commerce and
with their hands full; when they travel it is to spend their money,
not to live by their wits; they are too proud to cringe before strangers.
This is why they learn more abroad than the French who have other fish
to fry. Yet the English have their national prejudices; but these prejudices
are not so much the result of ignorance as of feeling. The Englishman's
prejudices are the result of pride, the Frenchman's are due to vanity.
Just as the least cultivated nations are usually the best, so those
travel best who travel least; they have made less progress than we in
our frivolous pursuits, they are less concerned with the objects of
our empty curiosity, so that they give their attention to what is really
useful. I hardly know any but the Spaniards who travel in this fashion.
While the Frenchman is running after all the artists of the country,
while the Englishman is getting a copy of some antique, while the German
is taking his album to every man of science, the Spaniard is silently
studying the government, the manners of the country, its police, and
he is the only one of the four who from all that he has seen will carry
home any observation useful to his own country.
The ancients travelled little, read little, and wrote few books; yet
we see in those books that remain to us, that they observed each other
more thoroughly than we observe our contemporaries. Without going back
to the days of Homer, the only poet who transports us to the country
he describes, we cannot deny to Herodotus the glory of having painted
manners in his history, though he does it rather by narrative than by
comment; still he does it better than all our historians whose books
are overladen with portraits and characters. Tacitus has described the
Germans of his time better than any author has described the Germans
of to-day. There can be no doubt that those who have devoted themselves
to ancient history know more about the Greeks, Carthaginians, Romans,
Gauls, and Persians than any nation of to-day knows about its neighbours.
It must also be admitted that the original characteristics of different
nations are changing day by day, and are therefore more difficult to
grasp. As races blend and nations intermingle, those national differences
which formerly struck the observer at first sight gradually disappear.
Before our time every nation remained more or less cut off from the
rest; the means of communication were fewer; there was less travelling,
less of mutual or conflicting interests, less political and civil intercourse
between nation and nation; those intricate schemes of royalty, miscalled
diplomacy, were less frequent; there were no permanent ambassadors resident
at foreign courts; long voyages were rare, there was little foreign
trade, and what little there was, was either the work of princes, who
employed foreigners, or of people of no account who had no influence
on others and did nothing to bring the nations together. The relations
between Europe and Asia in the present century are a hundredfold more
numerous than those between Gaul and Spain in the past; Europe alone
was less accessible than the whole world is now.
Moreover, the peoples of antiquity usually considered themselves as
the original inhabitants of their country; they had dwelt there so long
that all record was lost of the far-off times when their ancestors settled
there; they had been there so long that the place had made a lasting
impression on them; but in modern Europe the invasions of the barbarians,
following upon the Roman conquests, have caused an extraordinary confusion.
The Frenchmen of to-day are no longer the big fair men of old; the Greeks
are no longer beautiful enough to serve as a sculptor's model; the very
face of the Romans has changed as well as their character; the Persians,
originally from Tartary, are daily losing their native ugliness through
the intermixture of Circassian blood. Europeans are no longer Gauls,
Germans, Iberians, Allobroges; they are all Scythians, more or less
degenerate in countenance, and still more so in conduct.
This is why the ancient distinctions of race, the effect of soil and
climate, made a greater difference between nation and nation in respect
of temperament, looks, manners, and character than can be distinguished
in our own time, when the fickleness of Europe leaves no time for natural
causes to work, when the forests are cut down and the marshes drained,
when the earth is more generally, though less thoroughly, tilled, so
that the same differences between country and country can no longer
be detected even in purely physical features.
If they considered these facts perhaps people would not be in such a
hurry to ridicule Herodotus, Ctesias, Pliny for having described the
inhabitants of different countries each with its own peculiarities and
with striking differences which we no longer see. To recognise such
types of face we should need to see the men themselves; no change must
have passed over them, if they are to remain the same. If we could behold
all the people who have ever lived, who can doubt that we should find
greater variations between one century and another, than are now found
between nation and nation.
At the same time, while observation becomes more difficult, it is more
carelessly and badly done; this is another reason for the small success
of our researches into the natural history of the human race. The information
acquired by travel depends upon the object of the journey. If this object
is a system of philosophy, the traveller only sees what he desires to
see; if it is self-interest, it engrosses the whole attention of those
concerned. Commerce and the arts which blend and mingle the nations
at the same time prevent them from studying each other. If they know
how to make a profit out of their neighbours, what more do they need
to know?
It is a good thing to know all the places where we might live, so as
to choose those where we can live most comfortably. If every one lived
by his own efforts, all he would need to know would be how much land
would keep him in food. The savage, who has need of no one, and envies
no one, neither knows nor seeks to know any other country but his own.
If he requires more land for his subsistence he shuns inhabited places;
he makes war upon the wild beasts and feeds on them. But for us, to
whom civilised life has become a necessity, for us who must needs devour
our fellow-creatures, self-interest prompts each one of us to frequent
those districts where there are most people to be devoured. This is
why we all flock to Rome, Paris, and London. Human flesh and blood are
always cheapest in the capital cities. Thus we only know the great nations,
which are just like one another.
They say that men of learning travel to obtain information; not so,
they travel like other people from interested motives. Philosophers
like Plato and Pythagoras are no longer to be found, or if they are,
it must be in far-off lands. Our men of learning only travel at the
king's command; they are sent out, their expenses are paid, they receive
a salary for seeing such and such things, and the object of that journey
is certainly not the study of any question of morals. Their whole time
is required for the object of their journey, and they are too honest
not to earn their pay. If in any country whatsoever there are people
travelling at their own expense, you may be sure it is not to study
men but to teach them. It is not knowledge they desire but ostentation.
How should their travels teach them to shake off the yoke of prejudice?
It is prejudice that sends them on their travels.
To travel to see foreign lands or to see foreign nations are two very
different things. The former is the usual aim of the curious, the latter
is merely subordinate to it. If you wish to travel as a philosopher
you should reverse this order. The child observes things till he is
old enough to study men. Man should begin by studying his fellows; he
can study things later if time permits.
It is therefore illogical to conclude that travel is useless because
we travel ill. But granting the usefulness of travel, does it follow
that it is good for all of us? Far from it; there are very few people
who are really fit to travel; it is only good for those who are strong
enough in themselves to listen to the voice of error without being deceived,
strong enough to see the example of vice without being led away by it.
Travelling accelerates the progress of nature, and completes the man
for good or evil. When a man returns from travelling about the world,
he is what he will be all his life; there are more who return bad than
good, because there are more who start with an inclination towards evil.
In the course of their travels, young people, ill-educated and ill-behaved,
pick up all the vices of the nations among whom they have sojourned,
and none of the virtues with which those vices are associated; but those
who, happily for themselves, are well-born, those whose good disposition
has been well cultivated, those who travel with a real desire to learn,
all such return better and wiser than they went. Emile will travel in
this fashion; in this fashion there travelled another young man, worthy
of a nobler age; one whose worth was the admiration of Europe, one who
died for his country in the flower of his manhood; he deserved to live,
and his tomb, ennobled by his virtues only, received no honour till
a stranger's hand adorned it with flowers.
Everything that is done in reason should have its rules. Travel, undertaken
as a part of education, should therefore have its rules. To travel for
travelling's sake is to wander, to be a vagabond; to travel to learn
is still too vague; learning without some definite aim is worthless.
I would give a young man a personal interest in learning, and that interest,
well-chosen, will also decide the nature of the instruction. This is
merely the continuation of the method I have hitherto practised.
Now after he has considered himself in his physical relations to other
creatures, in his moral relations with other men, there remains to be
considered his civil relations with his fellow-citizens. To do this
he must first study the nature of government in general, then the different
forms of government, and lastly the particular government under which
he was born, to know if it suits him to live under it; for by a right
which nothing can abrogate, every man, when he comes of age, becomes
his own master, free to renounce the contract by which he forms part
of the community, by leaving the country in which that contract holds
good. It is only by sojourning in that country, after he has come to
years of discretion, that he is supposed to have tacitly confirmed the
pledge given by his ancestors. He acquires the right to renounce his
country, just as he has the right to renounce all claim to his father's
lands; yet his place of birth was a gift of nature, and in renouncing
it, he renounces what is his own. Strictly speaking, every man remains
in the land of his birth at his own risk unless he voluntarily submits
to its laws in order to acquire a right to their protection.
For example, I should say to Emile, "Hitherto you have lived under
my guidance, you were unable to rule yourself. But now you are approaching
the age when the law, giving you the control over your property, makes
you master of your person. You are about to find yourself alone in society,
dependent on everything, even on your patrimony. You mean to marry;
that is a praiseworthy intention, it is one of the duties of man; but
before you marry you must know what sort of man you want to be, how
you wish to spend your life, what steps you mean to take to secure a
living for your family and for yourself; for although we should not
make this our main business, it must be definitely considered. Do you
wish to be dependent on men whom you despise? Do you wish to establish
your fortune and determine your position by means of civil relations
which will make you always dependent on the choice of others, which
will compel you, if you would escape from knaves, to become a knave
yourself?"
In the next place I would show him every possible way of using his money
in trade, in the civil service, in finance, and I shall show him that
in every one of these there are risks to be taken, every one of them
places him in a precarious and dependent position, and compels him to
adapt his morals, his sentiments, his conduct to the example and the
prejudices of others.
"There is yet another way of spending your time and money; you
may join the army; that is to say, you may hire yourself out at very
high wages to go and kill men who never did you any harm. This trade
is held in great honour among men, and they cannot think too highly
of those who are fit for nothing better. Moreover, this profession,
far from making you independent of other resources, makes them all the
more necessary; for it is a point of honour in this profession to ruin
those who have adopted it. It is true they are not all ruined; it is
even becoming fashionable to grow rich in this as in other professions;
but if I told you how people manage to do it, I doubt whether you would
desire to follow their example.
"Moreover, you must know that, even in this trade, it is no longer
a question of courage or valour, unless with regard to the ladies; on
the contrary, the more cringing, mean, and degraded you are, the more
honour you obtain; if you have decided to take your profession seriously,
you will be despised, you will be hated, you will very possibly be driven
out of the service, or at least you will fall a victim to favouritism
and be supplanted by your comrades, because you have been doing your
duty in the trenches, while they have been attending to their toilet."
We can hardly suppose that any of these occupations will be much to
Emile's taste. "Why," he will exclaim, "have I forgotten
the amusements of my childhood? Have I lost the use of my arms? Is my
strength failing me? Do I not know how to work? What do I care about
all your fine professions and all the silly prejudices of others? I
know no other pride than to be kindly and just; no other happiness than
to live in independence with her I love, gaining health and a good appetite
by the day's work. All these difficulties you speak of do not concern
me. The only property I desire is a little farm in some quiet corner.
I will devote all my efforts after wealth to making it pay, and I will
live without a care. Give me Sophy and my land, and I shall be rich."
"Yes, my dear friend, that is all a wise man requires, a wife and
land of his own; but these treasures are scarcer than you think. The
rarest you have found already; let us discuss the other.
"A field of your own, dear Emile! Where will you find it, in what
remote corner of the earth can you say, 'Here am I master of myself
and of this estate which belongs to me?' We know where a man may grow
rich; who knows where he can do without riches? Who knows where to live
free and independent, without ill-treating others and without fear of
being ill-treated himself! Do you think it is so easy to find a place
where you can always live like an honest man? If there is any safe and
lawful way of living without intrigues, without lawsuits, without dependence
on others, it is, I admit, to live by the labour of our hands, by the
cultivation of our own land; but where is the state in which a man can
say, 'The earth which I dig is my own?' Before choosing this happy spot,
be sure that you will find the peace you desire; beware lest an unjust
government, a persecuting religion, and evil habits should disturb you
in your home. Secure yourself against the excessive taxes which devour
the fruits of your labours, and the endless lawsuits which consume your
capital. Take care that you can live rightly without having to pay court
to intendents, to their deputies, to judges, to priests, to powerful
neighbours, and to knaves of every kind, who are always ready to annoy
you if you neglect them. Above all, secure yourself from annoyance on
the part of the rich and great; remember that their estates may anywhere
adjoin your Naboth's vineyard. If unluckily for you some great man buys
or builds a house near your cottage, make sure that he will not find
a way, under some pretence or other, to encroach on your lands to round
off his estate, or that you do not find him at once absorbing all your
resources to make a wide highroad. If you keep sufficient credit to
ward off all these disagreeables, you might as well keep your money,
for it will cost you no more to keep it. Riches and credit lean upon
each other, the one can hardly stand without the other.
"I have more experience than you, dear Emile; I see more clearly
the difficulties in the way of your scheme. Yet it is a fine scheme
and honourable; it would make you happy indeed. Let us try to carry
it out. I have a suggestion to make; let us devote the two years from
now till the time of your return to choosing a place in Europe where
you could live happily with your family, secure from all the dangers
I have just described. If we succeed, you will have discovered that
true happiness, so often sought for in vain; and you will not have to
regret the time spent in its search. If we fail, you will be cured of
a mistaken idea; you will console yourself for an inevitable ill, and
you will bow to the law of necessity."
I do not know whether all my readers will see whither this suggested
inquiry will lead us; but this I do know, if Emile returns from his
travels, begun and continued with this end in view, without a full knowledge
of questions of government, public morality, and political philosophy
of every kind, we are greatly lacking, he in intelligence and I in judgment.
The science of politics is and probably always will be unknown. Grotius,
our leader in this branch of learning, is only a child, and what is
worse an untruthful child. When I hear Grotius praised to the skies
and Hobbes overwhelmed with abuse, I perceive how little sensible men
have read or understood these authors. As a matter of fact, their principles
are exactly alike, they only differ in their mode of expression. Their
methods are also different: Hobbes relies on sophism; Grotius relies
on the poets; they are agreed in everything else. In modern times the
only man who could have created this vast and useless science was the
illustrious Montesquieu. But he was not concerned with the principles
of political law; he was content to deal with the positive laws of settled
governments; and nothing could be more different than these two branches
of study.
Yet he who would judge wisely in matters of actual government is forced
to combine the two; he must know what ought to be in order to judge
what is. The chief difficulty in the way of throwing light upon this
important matter is to induce an individual to discuss and to answer
these two questions. "How does it concern me; and what can I do?"
Emile is in a position to answer both.
The next difficulty is due to the prejudices of childhood, the principles
in which we were brought up; it is due above all to the partiality of
authors, who are always talking about truth, though they care very little
about it; it is only their own interests that they care for, and of
these they say nothing. Now the nation has neither professorships, nor
pensions, nor membership of the academies to bestow. How then shall
its rights be established by men of that type? The education I have
given him has removed this difficulty also from Emile's path. He scarcely
knows what is meant by government; his business is to find the best;
he does not want to write books; if ever he did so, it would not be
to pay court to those in authority, but to establish the rights of humanity.
There is a third difficulty, more specious than real; a difficulty which
I neither desire to solve nor even to state; enough that I am not afraid
of it; sure I am that in inquiries of this kind, great talents are less
necessary than a genuine love of justice and a sincere reverence for
truth. If matters of government can ever be fairly discussed, now or
never is our chance.
Before beginning our observations we must lay down rules of procedure;
we must find a scale with which to compare our measurements. Our principles
of political law are our scale. Our actual measurements are the civil
law of each country.
Our elementary notions are plain and simple, being taken directly from
the nature of things. They will take the form of problems discussed
between us, and they will not be formulated into principles, until we
have found a satisfactory solution of our problems.
For example, we shall begin with the state of nature, we shall see whether
men are born slaves or free, in a community or independent; is their
association the result of free will or of force? Can the force which
compels them to united action ever form a permanent law, by which this
original force becomes binding, even when another has been imposed upon
it, so that since the power of King Nimrod, who is said to have been
the first conqueror, every other power which has overthrown the original
power is unjust and usurping, so that there are no lawful kings but
the descendants of Nimrod or their representatives; or if this original
power has ceased, has the power which succeeded it any right over us,
and does it destroy the binding force of the former power, so that we
are not bound to obey except under compulsion, and we are free to rebel
as soon as we are capable of resistance? Such a right is not very different
from might; it is little more than a play upon words.
We shall inquire whether man might not say that all sickness comes from
God, and that it is therefore a crime to send for the doctor.
Again, we shall inquire whether we are bound by our conscience to give
our purse to a highwayman when we might conceal it from him, for the
pistol in his hand is also a power.
Does this word power in this context mean something different from a
power which is lawful and therefore subject to the laws to which it
owes its being?
Suppose we reject this theory that might is right and admit the right
of nature, or the authority of the father, as the foundation of society;
we shall inquire into the extent of this authority; what is its foundation
in nature? Has it any other grounds but that of its usefulness to the
child, his weakness, and the natural love which his father feels towards
him? When the child is no longer feeble, when he is grown-up in mind
as well as in body, does not he become the sole judge of what is necessary
for his preservation? Is he not therefore his own master, independent
of all men, even of his father himself? For is it not still more certain
that the son loves himself, than that the father loves the son?
The father being dead, should the children obey the eldest brother,
or some other person who has not the natural affection of a father?
Should there always be, from family to family, one single head to whom
all the family owe obedience? If so, how has power ever come to be divided,
and how is it that there is more than one head to govern the human race
throughout the world?
Suppose the nations to have been formed each by its own choice; we shall
then distinguish between right and fact; being thus subjected to their
brothers, uncles, or other relations, not because they were obliged,
but because they choose, we shall inquire whether this kind of society
is not a sort of free and voluntary association?
Taking next the law of slavery, we shall inquire whether a man can make
over to another his right to himself, without restriction, without reserve,
without any kind of conditions; that is to say, can he renounce his
person, his life, his reason, his very self, can he renounce all morality
in his actions; in a word, can he cease to exist before his death, in
spite of nature who places him directly in charge of his own preservation,
in spite of reason and conscience which tell him what to do and what
to leave undone?
If there is any reservation or restriction in the deed of slavery, we
shall discuss whether this deed does not then become a true contract,
in which both the contracting powers, having in this respect no common
master, [Footnote: If they had such a common master, he would be no
other than the sovereign, and then the right of slavery resting on the
right of sovereignty would not be its origin.] remain their own judge
as to the conditions of the contract, and therefore free to this extent,
and able to break the contract as soon as it becomes hurtful.
If then a slave cannot convey himself altogether to his master, how
can a nation convey itself altogether to its head? If a slave is to
judge whether his master is fulfilling his contract, is not the nation
to judge whether its head is fulfilling his contract?
Thus we are compelled to retrace our steps, and when we consider the
meaning of this collective nation we shall inquire whether some contract,
a tacit contract at the least, is not required to make a nation, a contract
anterior to that which we are assuming.
Since the nation was a nation before it chose a king, what made it a
nation, except the social contract? Therefore the social contract is
the foundation of all civil society, and it is in the nature of this
contract that we must seek the nature of the society formed by it.
We will inquire into the meaning of this contract; may it not be fairly
well expressed in this formula? As an individual every one of us contributes
his goods, his person, his life, to the common stock, under the supreme
direction of the general will; while as a body we receive each member
as an indivisible part of the whole.
Assuming this, in order to define the terms we require, we shall observe
that, instead of the individual person of each contracting party, this
deed of association produces a moral and collective body, consisting
of as many members as there are votes in the Assembly. This public personality
is usually called the body politic, which is called by its members the
State when it is passive, and the Sovereign when it is active, and a
Power when compared with its equals. With regard to the members themselves,
collectively they are known as the nation, and individually as citizens
as members of the city or partakers in the sovereign power, and subjects
as obedient to the same authority.
We shall note that this contract of association includes a mutual pledge
on the part of the public and the individual; and that each individual,
entering, so to speak, into a contract with himself, finds himself in
a twofold capacity, i.e., as a member of the sovereign with regard to
others, as member of the state with regard to the sovereign.
We shall also note that while no one is bound by any engagement to which
he was not himself a party, the general deliberation which may be binding
on all the subjects with regard to the sovereign, because of the two
different relations under which each of them is envisaged, cannot be
binding on the state with regard to itself. Hence we see that there
is not, and cannot be, any other fundamental law, properly so called,
except the social contract only. This does not mean that the body politic
cannot, in certain respects, pledge itself to others; for in regard
to the foreigner, it then becomes a simple creature, an individual.
Thus the two contracting parties, i.e., each individual and the public,
have no common superior to decide their differences; so we will inquire
if each of them remains free to break the contract at will, that is
to repudiate it on his side as soon as he considers it hurtful.
To clear up this difficulty, we shall observe that, according to the
social pact, the sovereign power is only able to act through the common,
general will; so its decrees can only have a general or common aim;
hence it follows that a private individual cannot be directly injured
by the sovereign, unless all are injured, which is impossible, for that
would be to want to harm oneself. Thus the social contract has no need
of any warrant but the general power, for it can only be broken by individuals,
and they are not therefore freed from their engagement, but punished
for having broken it.
To decide all such questions rightly, we must always bear in mind that
the nature of the social pact is private and peculiar to itself, in
that the nation only contracts with itself, i.e., the people as a whole
as sovereign, with the individuals as subjects; this condition is essential
to the construction and working of the political machine, it alone makes
pledges lawful, reasonable, and secure, without which it would be absurd,
tyrannical, and liable to the grossest abuse.
Individuals having only submitted themselves to the sovereign, and the
sovereign power being only the general will, we shall see that every
man in obeying the sovereign only obeys himself, and how much freer
are we under the social part than in the state of nature.
Having compared natural and civil liberty with regard to persons, we
will compare them as to property, the rights of ownership and the rights
of sovereignty, the private and the common domain. If the sovereign
power rests upon the right of ownership, there is no right more worthy
of respect; it is inviolable and sacred for the sovereign power, so
long as it remains a private individual right; as soon as it is viewed
as common to all the citizens, it is subject to the common will, and
this will may destroy it. Thus the sovereign has no right to touch the
property of one or many; but he may lawfully take possession of the
property of all, as was done in Sparta in the time of Lycurgus; while
the abolition of debts by Solon was an unlawful deed.
Since nothing is binding on the subjects except the general will, let
us inquire how this will is made manifest, by what signs we may recognise
it with certainty, what is a law, and what are the true characters of
the law? This is quite a fresh subject; we have still to define the
term law.
As soon as the nation considers one or more of its members, the nation
is divided. A relation is established between the whole and its part
which makes of them two separate entities, of which the part is one,
and the whole, minus that part, is the other. But the whole minus the
part is not the whole; as long as this relation exists, there is no
longer a whole, but two unequal parts.
On the other hand, if the whole nation makes a law for the whole nation,
it is only considering itself; and if a relation is set up, it is between
the whole community regarded from one point of view, and the whole community
regarded from another point of view, without any division of that whole.
Then the object of the statute is general, and the will which makes
that statute is general too. Let us see if there is any other kind of
decree which may bear the name of law.
If the sovereign can only speak through laws, and if the law can never
have any but a general purpose, concerning all the members of the state,
it follows that the sovereign never has the power to make any law with
regard to particular cases; and yet it is necessary for the preservation
of the state that particular oases should also be dealt with; let us
see how this can be done.
The decrees of the sovereign can only be decrees of the general will,
that is laws; there must also be determining decrees, decrees of power
or government, for the execution of those laws; and these, on the other
hand, can only have particular aims. Thus the decrees by which the sovereign
decides that a chief shall be elected is a law; the decree by which
that chief is elected, in pursuance of the law, is only a decree of
government.
This is a third relation in which the assembled people may be considered,
i.e., as magistrates or executors of the law which it has passed in
its capacity as sovereign. [Footnote: These problems and theorems are
mostly taken from the Treatise on the Social Contract, itself a summary
of a larger work, undertaken without due consideration of my own powers,
and long since abandoned.]
We will now inquire whether it is possible for the nation to deprive
itself of its right of sovereignty, to bestow it on one or more persons;
for the decree of election not being a law, and the people in this decree
not being themselves sovereign, we do not see how they can transfer
a right which they do not possess.
The essence of sovereignty consisting in the general will, it is equally
hard to see how we can be certain that an individual will shall always
be in agreement with the general will. We should rather assume that
it will often be opposed to it; for individual interest always tends
to privileges, while the common interest always tends to equality, and
if such an agreement were possible, no sovereign right could exist,
unless the agreement were either necessary or indestructible.
We will inquire if, without violating the social pact, the heads of
the nation, under whatever name they are chosen, can ever be more than
the officers of the people, entrusted by them with the duty of carrying
the law into execution. Are not these chiefs themselves accountable
for their administration, and are not they themselves subject to the
laws which it is their business to see carried out?
If the nation cannot alienate its supreme right, can it entrust it to
others for a time? Cannot it give itself a master, cannot it find representatives?
This is an important question and deserves discussion.
If the nation can have neither sovereign nor representatives we will
inquire how it can pass its own laws; must there be many laws; must
they be often altered; is it easy for a great nation to be its own lawgiver?
Was not the Roman people a great nation?
Is it a good thing that there should be great nations?
It follows from considerations already established that there is an
intermediate body in the state between subjects and sovereign; and this
intermediate body, consisting of one or more members, is entrusted with
the public administration, the carrying out of the laws, and the maintenance
of civil and political liberty.
The members of this body are called magistrates or kings, that is to
say, rulers. This body, as a whole, considered in relation to its members,
is called the prince, and considered in its actions it is called the
government.
If we consider the action of the whole body upon itself, that is to
say, the relation of the whole to the whole, of the sovereign to the
state, we can compare this relation to that of the extremes in a proportion
of which the government is the middle term. The magistrate receives
from the sovereign the commands which he gives to the nation, and when
it is reckoned up his product or his power is in the same degree as
the product or power of the citizens who are subjects on one side of
the proportion and sovereigns on the other. None of the three terms
can be varied without at once destroying this proportion. If the sovereign
tries to govern, and if the prince wants to make the laws, or if the
subject refuses to obey them, disorder takes the place of order, and
the state falls to pieces under despotism or anarchy.
Let us suppose that this state consists of ten thousand citizens. The
sovereign can only be considered collectively and as a body, but each
individual, as a subject, has his private and independent existence.
Thus the sovereign is as ten thousand to one; that is to say, every
member of the state has, as his own share, only one ten-thousandth part
of the sovereign power, although he is subject to the whole. Let the
nation be composed of one hundred thousand men, the position of the
subjects is unchanged, and each continues to bear the whole weight of
the laws, while his vote, reduced to the one hundred-thousandth part,
has ten times less influence in the making of the laws. Thus the subject
being always one, the sovereign is relatively greater as the number
of the citizens is increased. Hence it follows that the larger the state
the less liberty.
Now the greater the disproportion between private wishes and the general
will, i.e., between manners and laws, the greater must be the power
of repression. On the other side, the greatness of the state gives the
depositaries of public authority greater temptations and additional
means of abusing that authority, so that the more power is required
by the government to control the people, the more power should there
be in the sovereign to control the government.
From this twofold relation it follows that the continued proportion
between the sovereign, the prince, and the people is not an arbitrary
idea, but a consequence of the nature of the state. Moreover, it follows
that one of the extremes, i.e., the nation, being constant, every time
the double ratio increases or decreases, the simple ratio increases
or diminishes in its turn; which cannot be unless the middle term is
as often changed. From this we may conclude that there is no single
absolute form of government, but there must be as many different forms
of government as there are states of different size.
If the greater the numbers of the nation the less the ratio between
its manners and its laws, by a fairly clear analogy, we may also say,
the more numerous the magistrates, the weaker the government.
To make this principle clearer we will distinguish three essentially
different wills in the person of each magistrate; first, his own will
as an individual, which looks to his own advantage only; secondly, the
common will of the magistrates, which is concerned only with the advantage
of the prince, a will which may be called corporate, and one which is
general in relation to the government and particular in relation to
the state of which the government forms part; thirdly, the will of the
people, or the sovereign will, which is general, as much in relation
to the state viewed as the whole as in relation to the government viewed
as a part of the whole. In a perfect legislature the private individual
will should be almost nothing; the corporate will belonging to the government
should be quite subordinate, and therefore the general and sovereign
will is the master of all the others. On the other hand, in the natural
order, these different wills become more and more active in proportion
as they become centralised; the general will is always weak, the corporate
will takes the second place, the individual will is preferred to all;
so that every one is himself first, then a magistrate, and then a citizen;
a series just the opposite of that required by the social order.
Having laid down this principle, let us assume that the government is
in the hands of one man. In this case the individual and the corporate
will are absolutely one, and therefore this will has reached the greatest
possible degree of intensity. Now the use of power depends on the degree
of this intensity, and as the absolute power of the government is always
that of the people, and therefore invariable, it follows that the rule
of one man is the most active form of government.
If, on the other hand, we unite the government with the supreme power,
and make the prince the sovereign and the citizens so many magistrates,
then the corporate will is completely lost in the general will, and
will have no more activity than the general will, and it will leave
the individual will in full vigour. Thus the government, though its
absolute force is constant, will have the minimum of activity.
These rules are incontestable in themselves, and other considerations
only serve to confirm them. For example, we see the magistrates as a
body far more active than the citizens as a body, so that the individual
will always counts for more. For each magistrate usually has charge
of some particular duty of government; while each citizen, in himself,
has no particular duty of sovereignty. Moreover, the greater the state
the greater its real power, although its power does not increase because
of the increase in territory; but the state remaining unchanged, the
magistrates are multiplied in vain, the government acquires no further
real strength, because it is the depositary of that of the state, which
I have assumed to be constant. Thus, this plurality of magistrates decreases
the activity of the government without increasing its power.
Having found that the power of the government is relaxed in proportion
as the number of magistrates is multiplied, and that the more numerous
the people, the more the controlling power must be increased, we shall
infer that the ratio between the magistrates and the government should
be inverse to that between subjects and sovereign, that is to say, that
the greater the state, the smaller the government, and that in like
manner the number of chiefs should be diminished because of the increased
numbers of the people.
In order to make this diversity of forms clearer, and to assign them
their different names, we shall observe in the first place that the
sovereign may entrust the care of the government to the whole nation
or to the greater part of the nation, so that there are more citizen
magistrates than private citizens. This form of government is called
Democracy.
Or the sovereign may restrict the government in the hands of a lesser
number, so that there are more plain citizens than magistrates; and
this form of government is called Aristocracy.
Finally, the sovereign may concentrate the whole government in the hands
of one man. This is the third and commonest form of government, and
is called Monarchy or royal government.
We shall observe that all these forms, or the first and second at least,
may be less or more, and that within tolerably wide limits. For the
democracy may include the whole nation, or may be confined to one half
of it. The aristocracy, in its turn, may shrink from the half of the
nation to the smallest number. Even royalty may be shared, either between
father and son, between two brothers, or in some other fashion. There
were always two kings in Sparta, and in the Roman empire there were
as many as eight emperors at once, and yet it cannot be said that the
empire was divided. There is a point where each form of government blends
with the next; and under the three specific forms there may be really
as many forms of government as there are citizens in the state.
Nor is this all. In certain respects each of these governments is capable
of subdivision into different parts, each administered in one of these
three ways. From these forms in combination there may arise a multitude
of mixed forms, since each may be multiplied by all the simple forms.
In all ages there have been great disputes as to which is the best form
of government, and people have failed to consider that each is the best
in some cases and the worst in others. For ourselves, if the number
of magistrates [Footnote: You will remember that I mean, in this context,
the supreme magistrates or heads of the nation, the others being only
their deputies in this or that respect.] in the various states is to
be in inverse ratio to the number of the citizens, we infer that generally
a democratic government is adapted to small states, an aristocratic
government to those of moderate size, and a monarchy to large states.
These inquiries furnish us with a clue by which we may discover what
are the duties and rights of citizens, and whether they can be separated
one from the other; what is our country, in what does it really consist,
and how can each of us ascertain whether he has a country or no?
Having thus considered every kind of civil society in itself, we shall
compare them, so as to note their relations one with another; great
and small, strong and weak, attacking one another, insulting one another,
destroying one another; and in this perpetual action and reaction causing
more misery and loss of life than if men had preserved their original
freedom. We shall inquire whether too much or too little has not been
accomplished in the matter of social institutions; whether individuals
who are subject to law and to men, while societies preserve the independence
of nature, are not exposed to the ills of both conditions without the
advantages of either, and whether it would not be better to have no
civil society in the world rather than to have many such societies.
Is it not that mixed condition which partakes of both and secures neither?
"Per quem neutrum licet, nec tanquam in bello paratum esse, nec
tanquam in pace securum."--Seneca De Trang: Animi, cap. I.
Is it not this partial and imperfect association which gives rise to
tyranny and war? And are not tyranny and war the worst scourges of humanity?
Finally we will inquire how men seek to get rid of these difficulties
by means of leagues and confederations, which leave each state its own
master in internal affairs, while they arm it against any unjust aggression.
We will inquire how a good federal association may be established, what
can make it lasting, and how far the rights of the federation may be
stretched without destroying the right of sovereignty.
The Abbe de Saint-Pierre suggested an association of all the states
of Europe to maintain perpetual peace among themselves. Is this association
practicable, and supposing that it were established, would it be likely
to last? These inquiries lead us straight to all the questions of international
law which may clear up the remaining difficulties of political law.
Finally we shall lay down the real principles of the laws of war, and
we shall see why Grotius and others have only stated false principles.
I should not be surprised if my pupil, who is a sensible young man,
should interrupt me saying, "One would think we were building our
edifice of wood and not of men; we are putting everything so exactly
in its place!" That is true; but remember that the law does not
bow to the passions of men, and that we have first to establish the
true principles of political law. Now that our foundations are laid,
come and see what men have built upon them; and you will see some strange
sights!
Then I set him to read Telemachus, and we pursue our journey; we are
seeking that happy Salentum and the good Idomeneus made wise by misfortunes.
By the way we find many like Protesilas and no Philocles, neither can
Adrastes, King of the Daunians, be found. But let our readers picture
our travels for themselves, or take the same journeys with Telemachus
in their hand; and let us not suggest to them painful applications which
the author himself avoids or makes in spite of himself.
Moreover, Emile is not a king, nor am I a god, so that we are not distressed
that we cannot imitate Telemachus and Mentor in the good they did; none
know better than we how to keep to our own place, none have less desire
to leave it. We know that the same task is allotted to all; that whoever
loves what is right with all his heart, and does the right so far as
it is in his power, has fulfilled that task. We know that Telemachus
and Mentor are creatures of the imagination. Emile does not travel in
idleness and he does more good than if he were a prince. If we were
kings we should be no greater benefactors. If we were kings and benefactors
we should cause any number of real evils for every apparent good we
supposed we were doing. If we were kings and sages, the first good deed
we should desire to perform, for ourselves and for others, would be
to abdicate our kingship and return to our present position.
I have said why travel does so little for every one. What makes it still
more barren for the young is the way in which they are sent on their
travels. Tutors, more concerned to amuse than to instruct, take them
from town to town, from palace to palace, where if they are men of learning
and letters, they make them spend their time in libraries, or visiting
antiquaries, or rummaging among old buildings transcribing ancient inscriptions.
In every country they are busy over some other century, as if they were
living in another country; so that after they have travelled all over
Europe at great expense, a prey to frivolity or tedium, they return,
having seen nothing to interest them, and having learnt nothing that
could be of any possible use to them.
All capitals are just alike, they are a mixture of all nations and all
ways of living; they are not the place in which to study the nations.
Paris and London seem to me the same town. Their inhabitants have a
few prejudices of their own, but each has as many as the other, and
all their rules of conduct are the same. We know the kind of people
who will throng the court. We know the way of living which the crowds
of people and the unequal distribution of wealth will produce. As soon
as any one tells me of a town with two hundred thousand people, I know
its life already. What I do not know about it is not worth going there
to learn.
To study the genius and character of a nation you should go to the more
remote provinces, where there is less stir, less commerce, where strangers
seldom travel, where the inhabitants stay in one place, where there
are fewer changes of wealth and position. Take a look at the capital
on your way, but go and study the country far away from that capital.
The French are not in Paris, but in Touraine; the English are more English
in Mercia than in London, and the Spaniards more Spanish in Galicia
than in Madrid. In these remoter provinces a nation assumes its true
character and shows what it really is; there the good or ill effects
of the government are best perceived, just as you can measure the arc
more exactly at a greater radius.
The necessary relations between character and government have been so
clearly pointed out in the book of L'Esprit des Lois, that one cannot
do better than have recourse to that work for the study of those relations.
But speaking generally, there are two plain and simple standards by
which to decide whether governments are good or bad. One is the population.
Every country in which the population is decreasing is on its way to
ruin; and the countries in which the population increases most rapidly,
even were they the poorest countries in the world, are certainly the
best governed. [Footnote: I only know one exception to this rule--it
is China.] But this population must be the natural result of the government
and the national character, for if it is caused by colonisation or any
other temporary and accidental cause, then the remedy itself is evidence
of the disease. When Augustus passed laws against celibacy, those laws
showed that the Roman empire was already beginning to decline. Citizens
must be induced to marry by the goodness of the government, not compelled
to marry by law; you must not examine the effects of force, for the
law which strives against the constitution has little or no effect;
you should study what is done by the influence of public morals and
by the natural inclination of the government, for these alone produce
a lasting effect. It was the policy of the worthy Abbe de Saint-Pierre
always to look for a little remedy for every individual ill, instead
of tracing them to their common source and seeing if they could not
all be cured together. You do not need to treat separately every sore
on a rich man's body; you should purify the blood which produces them.
They say that in England there are prizes for agriculture; that is enough
for me; that is proof enough that agriculture will not flourish there
much longer.
The second sign of the goodness or badness of the government and the
laws is also to be found in the population, but it is to be found not
in its numbers but in its distribution. Two states equal in size and
population may be very unequal in strength; and the more powerful is
always that in which the people are more evenly distributed over its
territory; the country which has fewer large towns, and makes less show
on this account, will always defeat the other. It is the great towns
which exhaust the state and are the cause of its weakness; the wealth
which they produce is a sham wealth, there is much money and few goods.
They say the town of Paris is worth a whole province to the King of
France; for my own part I believe it costs him more than several provinces.
I believe that Paris is fed by the provinces in more senses than one,
and that the greater part of their revenues is poured into that town
and stays there, without ever returning to the people or to the king.
It is inconceivable that in this age of calculators there is no one
to see that France would be much more powerful if Paris were destroyed.
Not only is this ill-distributed population not advantageous to the
state, it is more ruinous than depopulation itself, because depopulation
only gives as produce nought, and the ill-regulated addition of still
more people gives a negative result. When I hear an Englishman and a
Frenchman so proud of the size of their capitals, and disputing whether
London or Paris has more inhabitants, it seems to me that they are quarrelling
as to which nation can claim the honour of being the worst governed.
Study the nation outside its towns; thus only will you really get to
know it. It is nothing to see the apparent form of a government, overladen
with the machinery of administration and the jargon of the administrators,
if you have not also studied its nature as seen in the effects it has
upon the people, and in every degree of administration. The difference
of form is really shared by every degree of the administration, and
it is only by including every degree that you really know the difference.
In one country you begin to feel the spirit of the minister in the manoeuvres
of his underlings; in another you must see the election of members of
parliament to see if the nation is really free; in each and every country,
he who has only seen the towns cannot possibly know what the government
is like, as its spirit is never the same in town and country. Now it
is the agricultural districts which form the country, and the country
people who make the nation.
This study of different nations in their remoter provinces, and in the
simplicity of their native genius, gives a general result which is very
satisfactory, to my thinking, and very consoling to the human heart;
it is this: All the nations, if you observe them in this fashion, seem
much better worth observing; the nearer they are to nature, the more
does kindness hold sway in their character; it is only when they are
cooped up in towns, it is only when they are changed by cultivation,
that they become depraved, that certain faults which were rather coarse
than injurious are exchanged for pleasant but pernicious vices.
From this observation we see another advantage in the mode of travel
I suggest; for young men, sojourning less in the big towns which are
horribly corrupt, are less likely to catch the infection of vice; among
simpler people and less numerous company, they will preserve a surer
judgment, a healthier taste, and better morals. Besides this contagion
of vice is hardly to be feared for Emile; he has everything to protect
him from it. Among all the precautions I have taken, I reckon much on
the love he bears in his heart.
We do not know the power of true love over youthful desires, because
we are ourselves as ignorant of it as they are, and those who have control
over the young turn them from true love. Yet a young man must either
love or fall into bad ways. It is easy to be deceived by appearances.
You will quote any number of young men who are said to live very chastely
without love; but show me one grown man, a real man, who can truly say
that his youth was thus spent? In all our virtues, all our duties, people
are content with appearances; for my own part I want the reality, and
I am much mistaken if there is any other way of securing it beyond the
means I have suggested.
The idea of letting Emile fall in love before taking him on his travels
is not my own. It was suggested to me by the following incident.
I was in Venice calling on the tutor of a young Englishman. It was winter
and we were sitting round the fire. The tutor's letters were brought
from the post office. He glanced at them, and then read them aloud to
his pupil. They were in English; I understood not a word, but while
he was reading I saw the young man tear some fine point lace ruffles
which he was wearing, and throw them in the fire one after another,
as quietly as he could, so that no one should see it. Surprised at this
whim, I looked at his face and thought I perceived some emotion; but
the external signs of passion, though much alike in all men, have national
differences which may easily lead one astray. Nations have a different
language of facial expression as well as of speech. I waited till the
letters were finished and then showing the tutor the bare wrists of
his pupil, which he did his best to hide, I said, "May I ask the
meaning of this?"
The tutor seeing what had happened began to laugh; he embraced his pupil
with an air of satisfaction and, with his consent, he gave me the desired
explanation.
"The ruffles," said he, "which Mr. John has just torn
to pieces, were a present from a lady in this town, who made them for
him not long ago. Now you must know that Mr. John is engaged to a young
lady in his own country, with whom he is greatly in love, and she well
deserves it. This letter is from the lady's mother, and I will translate
the passage which caused the destruction you beheld.
"'Lucy is always at work upon Mr. John's ruffles. Yesterday Miss
Betty Roldham came to spend the afternoon and insisted on doing some
of her work. I knew that Lucy was up very early this morning and I wanted
to see what she was doing; I found her busy unpicking what Miss Betty
had done. She would not have a single stitch in her present done by
any hand but her own.'"
Mr. John went to fetch another pair of ruffles, and I said to his tutor:
"Your pupil has a very good disposition; but tell me is not the
letter from Miss Lucy's mother a put up job? Is it not an expedient
of your designing against the lady of the ruffles?" "No,"
said he, "it is quite genuine; I am not so artful as that; I have
made use of simplicity and zeal, and God has blessed my efforts."
This incident with regard to the young man stuck in my mind; it was
sure to set a dreamer like me thinking.
But it is time we finished. Let us take Mr. John back to Miss Lucy,
or rather Emile to Sophy. He brings her a heart as tender as ever, and
a more enlightened mind, and he returns to his native land all the bettor
for having made acquaintance with foreign governments through their
vices and foreign nations through their virtues. I have even taken care
that he should associate himself with some man of worth in every nation,
by means of a treaty of hospitality after the fashion of the ancients,
and I shall not be sorry if this acquaintance is kept up by means of
letters. Not only may this be useful, not only is it always pleasant
to have a correspondent in foreign lands, it is also an excellent antidote
against the sway of patriotic prejudices, to which we are liable all
through our life, and to which sooner or later we are more or less enslaved.
Nothing is better calculated to lessen the hold of such prejudices than
a friendly interchange of opinions with sensible people whom we respect;
they are free from our prejudices and we find ourselves face to face
with theirs, and so we can set the one set of prejudices against the
other and be safe from both. It is not the same thing to have to do
with strangers in our own country and in theirs. In the former case
there is always a certain amount of politeness which either makes them
conceal their real opinions, or makes them think more favourably of
our country while they are with us; when they get home again this disappears,
and they merely do us justice. I should be very glad if the foreigner
I consult has seen my country, but I shall not ask what he thinks of
it till he is at home again.
When we have spent nearly two years travelling in a few of the great
countries and many of the smaller countries of Europe, when we have
learnt two or three of the chief languages, when we have seen what is
really interesting in natural history, government, arts, or men, Emile,
devoured by impatience, reminds me that our time is almost up. Then
I say, "Well, my friend, you remember the main object of our journey;
you have seen and observed; what is the final result of your observations?
What decision have you come to?" Either my method is wrong, or
he will answer me somewhat after this fashion--
"What decision have I come to? I have decided to be what you made
me; of my own free will I will add no fetters to those imposed upon
me by nature and the laws. The more I study the works of men in their
institutions, the more clearly I see that, in their efforts after independence,
they become slaves, and that their very freedom is wasted in vain attempts
to assure its continuance. That they may not be carried away by the
flood of things, they form all sorts of attachments; then as soon as
they wish to move forward they are surprised to find that everything
drags them back. It seems to me that to set oneself free we need do
nothing, we need only continue to desire freedom. My master, you have
made me free by teaching me to yield to necessity. Let her come when
she will, I follow her without compulsion; I lay hold of nothing to
keep me back. In our travels I have sought for some corner of the earth
where I might be absolutely my own; but where can one dwell among men
without being dependent on their passions? On further consideration
I have discovered that my desire contradicted itself; for were I to
hold to nothing else, I should at least hold to the spot on which I
had settled; my life would be attached to that spot, as the dryads were
attached to their trees. I have discovered that the words liberty and
empire are incompatible; I can only be master of a cottage by ceasing
to be master of myself.
"'Hoc erat in votis, modus agri non ita magnus.' Horace, lib. ii.,
sat. vi.
"I remember that my property was the origin of our inquiries. You
argued very forcibly that I could not keep both my wealth and my liberty;
but when you wished me to be free and at the same time without needs,
you desired two incompatible things, for I could only be independent
of men by returning to dependence on nature. What then shall I do with
the fortune bequeathed to me by my parents? To begin with, I will not
be dependent on it; I will cut myself loose from all the ties which
bind me to it; if it is left in my hands, I shall keep it; if I am deprived
of it, I shall not be dragged away with it. I shall not trouble myself
to keep it, but I shall keep steadfastly to my own place. Rich or poor,
I shall be free. I shall be free not merely in this country or in that;
I shall be free in any part of the world. All the chains of prejudice
are broken; as far as I am concerned I know only the bonds of necessity.
I have been trained to endure them from my childhood, and I shall endure
them until death, for I am a man; and why should I not wear those chains
as a free man, for I should have to wear them even if I were a slave,
together with the additional fetters of slavery?
"What matters my place in the world? What matters it where I am?
Wherever there are men, I am among my brethren; wherever there are none,
I am in my own home. So long as I may be independent and rich, and have
wherewithal to live, and I shall live. If my wealth makes a slave of
me, I shall find it easy to renounce it. I have hands to work, and I
shall get a living. If my hands fail me, I shall live if others will
support me; if they forsake me I shall die; I shall die even if I am
not forsaken, for death is not the penalty of poverty, it is a law of
nature. Whensoever death comes I defy it; it shall never find me making
preparations for life; it shall never prevent me having lived.
"My father, this is my decision. But for my passions, I should
be in my manhood independent as God himself, for I only desire what
is and I should never fight against fate. At least, there is only one
chain, a chain which I shall ever wear, a chain of which I may be justly
proud. Come then, give me my Sophy, and I am free."
"Dear Emile, I am glad indeed to hear you speak like a man, and
to behold the feelings of your heart. At your age this exaggerated unselfishness
is not unpleasing. It will decrease when you have children of your own,
and then you will be just what a good father and a wise man ought to
be. I knew what the result would be before our travels; I knew that
when you saw our institutions you would be far from reposing a confidence
in them which they do not deserve. In vain do we seek freedom under
the power of the laws. The laws! Where is there any law? Where is there
any respect for law? Under the name of law you have everywhere seen
the rule of self-interest and human passion. But the eternal laws of
nature and of order exist. For the wise man they take the place of positive
law; they are written in the depths of his heart by conscience and reason;
let him obey these laws and be free; for there is no slave but the evil-doer,
for he always does evil against his will. Liberty is not to be found
in any form of government, she is in the heart of the free man, he bears
her with him everywhere. The vile man bears his slavery in himself;
the one would be a slave in Geneva, the other free in Paris.
"If I spoke to you of the duties of a citizen, you would perhaps
ask me, 'Which is my country?' And you would think you had put me to
confusion. Yet you would be mistaken, dear Emile, for he who has no
country has, at least, the land in which he lives. There is always a
government and certain so-called laws under which he has lived in peace.
What matter though the social contract has not been observed, if he
has been protected by private interest against the general will, if
he has been secured by public violence against private aggressions,
if the evil he has beheld has taught him to love the good, and if our
institutions themselves have made him perceive and hate their own iniquities?
Oh, Emile, where is the man who owes nothing to the land in which he
lives? Whatever that land may be, he owes to it the most precious thing
possessed by man, the morality of his actions and the love of virtue.
Born in the depths of a forest he would have lived in greater happiness
and freedom; but being able to follow his inclinations without a struggle
there would have been no merit in his goodness, he would not have been
virtuous, as he may be now, in spite of his passions. The mere sight
of order teaches him to know and love it. The public good, which to
others is a mere pretext, is a real motive for him. He learns to fight
against himself and to prevail, to sacrifice his own interest to the
common weal. It is not true that he gains nothing from the laws; they
give him courage to be just, even in the midst of the wicked. It is
not true that they have failed to make him free; they have taught him
to rule himself.
"Do not say therefore, 'What matter where I am?' It does matter
that you should be where you can best do your duty; and one of these
duties is to love your native land. Your fellow-countrymen protected
you in childhood; you should love them in your manhood. You should live
among them, or at least you should live where you can serve them to
the best of your power, and where they know where to find you if ever
they are in need of you. There are circumstances in which a man may
be of more use to his fellow-countrymen outside his country than within
it. Then he should listen only to his own zeal and should bear his exile
without a murmur; that exile is one of his duties. But you, dear Emile,
you have not undertaken the painful task of telling men the truth, you
must live in the midst of your fellow-creatures, cultivating their friendship
in pleasant intercourse; you must be their benefactor, their pattern;
your example will do more than all our books, and the good they see
you do will touch them more deeply than all our empty words.
"Yet I do not exhort you to live in a town; on the contrary, one
of the examples which the good should give to others is that of a patriarchal,
rural life, the earliest life of man, the most peaceful, the most natural,
and the most attractive to the uncorrupted heart. Happy is the land,
my young friend, where one need not seek peace in the wilderness! But
where is that country? A man of good will finds it hard to satisfy his
inclinations in the midst of towns, where he can find few but frauds
and rogues to work for. The welcome given by the towns to those idlers
who flock to them to seek their fortunes only completes the ruin of
the country, when the country ought really to be repopulated at the
cost of the towns. All the men who withdraw from high society are useful
just because of their withdrawal, since its vices are the result of
its numbers. They are also useful when they can bring with them into
the desert places life, culture, and the love of their first condition.
I like to think what benefits Emile and Sophy, in their simple home,
may spread about them, what a stimulus they may give to the country,
how they may revive the zeal of the unlucky villagers.
"In fancy I see the population increasing, the land coming under
cultivation, the earth clothed with fresh beauty. Many workers and plenteous
crops transform the labours of the fields into holidays; I see the young
couple in the midst of the rustic sports which they have revived, and
I hear the shouts of joy and the blessings of those about them. Men
say the golden age is a fable; it always will be for those whose feelings
and taste are depraved. People do not really regret the golden age,
for they do nothing to restore it. What is needed for its restoration?
One thing only, and that is an impossibility; we must love the golden
age.
"Already it seems to be reviving around Sophy's home; together
you will only complete what her worthy parents have begun. But, dear
Emile, you must not let so pleasant a life give you a distaste for sterner
duties, if every they are laid upon you; remember that the Romans sometimes
left the plough to become consul. If the prince or the state calls you
to the service of your country, leave all to fulfil the honourable duties
of a citizen in the post assigned to you. If you find that duty onerous,
there is a sure and honourable means of escaping from it; do your duty
so honestly that it will not long be left in your hands. Moreover, you
need not fear the difficulties of such a test; while there are men of
our own time, they will not summon you to serve the state."
Why may I not paint the return of Emile to Sophy and the end of their
love, or rather the beginning of their wedded love! A love founded on
esteem which will last with life itself, on virtues which will not fade
with fading beauty, on fitness of character which gives a charm to intercourse,
and prolongs to old age the delights of early love. But all such details
would be pleasing but not useful, and so far I have not permitted myself
to give attractive details unless I thought they would be useful. Shall
I abandon this rule when my task is nearly ended? No, I feel that my
pen is weary. Too feeble for such prolonged labours, I should abandon
this if it were not so nearly completed; if it is not to be left imperfect
it is time it were finished.
At last I see the happy day approaching, the happiest day of Emile's
life and my own; I see the crown of my labours, I begin to appreciate
their results. The noble pair are united till death do part; heart and
lips confirm no empty vows; they are man and wife. When they return
from the church, they follow where they are led; they know not where
they are, whither they are going, or what is happening around them.
They heed nothing, they answer at random; their eyes are troubled and
they see nothing. Oh, rapture! Oh, human weakness! Man is overwhelmed
by the feeling of happiness, he is not strong enough to bear it.
There are few people who know how to talk to the newly-married couple.
The gloomy propriety of some and the light conversation of others seem
to me equally out of place. I would rather their young hearts were left
to themselves, to abandon themselves to an agitation which is not without
its charm, rather than that they should be so cruelly distressed by
a false modesty, or annoyed by coarse witticisms which, even if they
appealed to them at other times, are surely out of place on such a day.
I behold our young people, wrapped in a pleasant languor, giving no
heed to what is said. Shall I, who desire that they should enjoy all
the days of their life, shall I let them lose this precious day? No,
I desire that they shall taste its pleasures and enjoy them. I rescue
them from the foolish crowd, and walk with them in some quiet place;
I recall them to themselves by speaking of them I wish to speak, not
merely to their ears, but to their hearts, and I know that there is
only one subject of which they can think to-day.
"My children," say I, taking a hand of each, "it is three
years since I beheld the birth of the pure and vigorous passion which
is your happiness to-day. It has gone on growing; your eyes tell me
that it has reached its highest point; it must inevitably decline."
My readers can fancy the raptures, the anger, the vows of Emile, and
the scornful air with which Sophy withdraws her hand from mine; how
their eyes protest that they will adore each other till their latest
breath. I let them have their way; then I continue:
"I have often thought that if the happiness of love could continue
in marriage, we should find a Paradise upon earth. So far this has never
been. But if it were not quite impossible, you two are quite worthy
to set an example you have not received, an example which few married
couples could follow. My children, shall I tell you what I think is
the way, and the only way, to do it?"
They look at one another and smile at my simplicity. Emile thanks me
curtly for my prescription, saying that he thinks Sophy has a better,
at any rate it is good enough for him. Sophy agrees with him and seems
just as certain. Yet in spite of her mockery, I think I see a trace
of curiosity. I study Emile; his eager eyes are fixed upon his wife's
beauty; he has no curiosity for anything else; and he pays little heed
to what I say. It is my turn to smile, and I say to myself, "I
will soon get your attention."
The almost imperceptible difference between these two hidden impulses
is characteristic of a real difference between the two sexes; it is
that men are generally less constant than women, and are sooner weary
of success in love. A woman foresees man's future inconstancy, and is
anxious; it is this which makes her more jealous. [Footnote: In France
it is the wives who first emancipate themselves; and necessarily so,
for having very little heart, and only desiring attention, when a husband
ceases to pay them attention they care very little for himself. In other
countries it is not so; it is the husband who first emancipates himself;
and necessarily so, for women, faithful, but foolish, importune men
with their desires and only disgust them. There may be plenty of exceptions
to these general truths; but I still think they are truths.] When his
passion begins to cool she is compelled to pay him the attentions he
used to bestow on her for her pleasure; she weeps, it is her turn to
humiliate herself, and she is rarely successful. Affection and kind
deeds rarely win hearts, and they hardly ever win them back. I return
to my prescription against the cooling of love in marriage.
"It is plain and simple," I continue. "It consists in
remaining lovers when you are husband and wife."
"Indeed," said Emile, laughing at my secret, "we shall
not find that hard."
"Perhaps you will find it harder than you think. Pray give me time
to explain.
"Cords too tightly stretched are soon broken. This is what happens
when the marriage bond is subjected to too great a strain. The fidelity
imposed by it upon husband and wife is the most sacred of all rights;
but it gives to each too great a power over the other. Constraint and
love do not agree together, and pleasure is not to be had for the asking.
Do not blush, Sophy, and do not try to run away. God forbid that I should
offend your modesty! But your fate for life is at stake. For so great
a cause, permit a conversation between your husband and your father
which you would not permit elsewhere.
"It is not so much possession as mastery of which people tire,
and affection is often more prolonged with regard to a mistress than
a wife. How can people make a duty of the tenderest caresses, and a
right of the sweetest pledges of love? It is mutual desire which gives
the right, and nature knows no other. The law may restrict this right,
it cannot extend it. The pleasure is so sweet in itself! Should it owe
to sad constraint the power which it cannot gain from its own charms?
No, my children, in marriage the hearts are bound, but the bodies are
not enslaved. You owe one another fidelity, but not complaisance. Neither
of you may give yourself to another, but neither of you belongs to the
other except at your own will.
"If it is true, dear Emile, that you would always be your wife's
lover, that she should always be your mistress and her own, be a happy
but respectful lover; obtain all from love and nothing from duty, and
let the slightest favours never be of right but of grace. I know that
modesty shuns formal confessions and requires to be overcome; but with
delicacy and true love, will the lover ever be mistaken as to the real
will? Will not he know when heart and eyes grant what the lips refuse?
Let both for ever be master of their person and their caresses, let
them have the right to bestow them only at their own will. Remember
that even in marriage this pleasure is only lawful when the desire is
mutual. Do not be afraid, my children, that this law will keep you apart;
on the contrary, it will make both more eager to please, and will prevent
satiety. True to one another, nature and love will draw you to each
other."
Emile is angry and cries out against these and similar suggestions.
Sophy is ashamed, she hides her face behind her fan and says nothing.
Perhaps while she is saying nothing, she is the most annoyed. Yet I
insist, without mercy; I make Emile blush for his lack of delicacy;
I undertake to be surety for Sophy that she will undertake her share
of the treaty. I incite her to speak, you may guess she will not dare
to say I am mistaken. Emile anxiously consults the eyes of his young
wife; he beholds them, through all her confusion, filled with a, voluptuous
anxiety which reassures him against the dangers of trusting her. He
flings himself at her feet, kisses with rapture the hand extended to
him, and swears that beyond the fidelity he has already promised, he
will renounce all other rights over her. "My dear wife," said
he, "be the arbiter of my pleasures as you are already the arbiter
of my life and fate. Should your cruelty cost me life itself I would
yield to you my most cherished rights. I will owe nothing to your complaisance,
but all to your heart."
Dear Emile, be comforted; Sophy herself is too generous to let you fall
a victim to your generosity.
In the evening, when I am about to leave them, I say in the most solemn
tone, "Remember both of you, that you are free, that there is no
question of marital rights; believe me, no false deference. Emile will
you come home with me? Sophy permits it." Emile is ready to strike
me in his anger. "And you, Sophy, what do you say? Shall I take
him away?" The little liar, blushing, answers, "Yes."
A tender and delightful falsehood, better than truth itself!
The next day. ... Men no longer delight in the picture of bliss; their
taste is as much depraved by the corruption of vice as their hearts.
They can no longer feel what is touching or perceive what is truly delightful.
You who, as a picture of voluptuous joys, see only the happy lovers
immersed in pleasure, your picture is very imperfect; you have only
its grosser part, the sweetest charms of pleasure are not there. Which
of you has seen a young couple, happily married, on the morrow of their
marriage? their chaste yet languid looks betray the intoxication of
the bliss they have enjoyed, the blessed security of innocence, and
the delightful certainty that they will spend the rest of their life
together. The heart of man can behold no more rapturous sight; this
is the real picture of happiness; you have beheld it a hundred times
without heeding it; your hearts are so hard that you cannot love it.
Sophy, peaceful and happy, spends the day in the arms of her tender
mother; a pleasant resting place, after a night spent in the arms of
her husband.
The day after I am aware of a slight change. Emile tries to look somewhat
vexed; but through this pretence I notice such a tender eagerness, and
indeed so much submission, that I do not think there is much amiss.
As for Sophy she is merrier than she was yesterday; her eyes are sparkling
and she looks very well pleased with herself; she is charming to Emile;
she ventures to tease him a little and vexes him still more.
These changes are almost imperceptible, but they do not escape me; I
am anxious and I question Emile in private, and I learn that, to his
great regret, and in spite of all entreaties, he was not permitted last
night to share Sophy's bed. That haughty lady had made haste to assert
her right. An explanation takes place. Emile complains bitterly, Sophy
laughs; but at last, seeing that Emile is really getting angry, she
looks at him with eyes full of tenderness and love, and pressing my
hand, she only says these two words, but in a tone that goes to his
heart, "Ungrateful man!" Emile is too stupid to understand.
But I understand, and I send Emile away and speak to Sophy privately
in her turn.
"I see," said I, "the reason for this whim. No one could
be more delicate, and no one could use that delicacy so ill. Dear Sophy,
do not be anxious, I have given you a man; do not be afraid to treat
him as such. You have had the first fruits of his youth; he has not
squandered his manhood and it will endure for you. My dear child, I
must explain to you why I said what I did in our conversation of the
day before yesterday. Perhaps you only understood it as a way of restraining
your pleasures to secure their continuance. Oh, Sophy, there was another
object, more worthy of my care. When Emile became your husband, he became
your head, it is yours to obey; this is the will of nature. When the
wife is like Sophy, it is, however, good for the man to be led by her;
that is another of nature's laws, and it is to give you as much authority
over his heart, as his sex gives him over your person, that I have made
you the arbiter of his pleasures. It will be hard for you, but you will
control him if you can control yourself, and what has already happened
shows me that this difficult art is not beyond your courage. You will
long rule him by love if you make your favours scarce and precious,
if you know how to use them aright. If you want to have your husband
always in your power, keep him at a distance. But let your sternness
be the result of modesty not caprice; let him find you modest not capricious;
beware lest in controlling his love you make him doubt your own. Be
all the dearer for your favours and all the more respected when you
refuse them; let him honour his wife's chastity, without having to complain
of her coldness.
"Thus, my child, he will give you his confidence, he will listen
to your opinion, will consult you in his business, and will decide nothing
without you. Thus you may recall him to wisdom, if he strays, and bring
him back by a gentle persuasion, you may make yourself lovable in order
to be useful, you may employ coquetry on behalf of virtue, and love
on behalf of reason.
"Do not think that with all this, your art will always serve your
purpose. In spite of every precaution pleasures are destroyed by possession,
and love above all others. But when love has lasted long enough, a gentle
habit takes its place and the charm of confidence succeeds the raptures
of passion. Children form a bond between their parents, a bond no less
tender and a bond which is sometimes stronger than love itself. When
you cease to be Emile's mistress you will be his friend and wife; you
will be the mother of his children. Then instead of your first reticence
let there be the fullest intimacy between you; no more separate beds,
no more refusals, no more caprices. Become so truly his better half
that he can no longer do without you, and if he must leave you, let
him feel that he is far from himself. You have made the charms of home
life so powerful in your father's home, let them prevail in your own.
Every man who is happy at home loves his wife. Remember that if your
husband is happy in his home, you will be a happy wife.
"For the present, do not be too hard on your lover; he deserves
more consideration; he will be offended by your fears; do not care for
his health at the cost of his happiness, and enjoy your own happiness.
You must neither wait for disgust nor repulse desire; you must not refuse
for the sake of refusing, but only to add to the value of your favours."
Then, taking her back to Emile, I say to her young husband, "One
must bear the yoke voluntarily imposed upon oneself. Let your deserts
be such that the yoke may be lightened. Above all, sacrifice to the
graces, and do not think that sulkiness will make you more amiable."
Peace is soon made, and everybody can guess its terms. The treaty is
signed with a kiss, after which I say to my pupil, "Dear Emile,
all his life through a man needs a guide and counsellor. So far I have
done my best to fulfil that duty; my lengthy task is now ended, and
another will undertake this duty. To-day I abdicate the authority which
you gave me; henceforward Sophy is your guardian."
Little by little the first raptures subside and they can peacefully
enjoy the delights of their new condition. Happy lovers, worthy husband
and wife! To do honour to their virtues, to paint their felicity, would
require the history of their lives. How often does my heart throb with
rapture when I behold in them the crown of my life's work! How often
do I take their hands in mine blessing God with all my heart! How often
do I kiss their clasped hands! How often do their tears of joy fall
upon mine! They are touched by my joy and they share my raptures. Their
worthy parents see their own youth renewed in that of their children;
they begin to live, as it were, afresh in them; or rather they perceive,
for the first time, the true value of life; they curse their former
wealth, which prevented them from enjoying so delightful a lot when
they were young. If there is such a thing as happiness upon earth, you
must seek it in our abode.
One morning a few months later Emile enters my room and embraces me,
saying, "My master, congratulate your son; he hopes soon to have
the honour of being a father. What a responsibility will be ours, how
much we shall need you! Yet God forbid that I should let you educate
the son as you educated the father. God forbid that so sweet and holy
a task should be fulfilled by any but myself, even though I should make
as good a choice for my child as was made for me! But continue to be
the teacher of the young teachers. Advise and control us; we shall be
easily led; as long as I live I shall need you. I need you more than
ever now that I am taking up the duties of manhood. You have done your
own duty; teach me to follow your example, while you enjoy your well-earned
leisure."
|